As our knowledge of
surgical and diagnostic techniques has increased with time, so has the success
rate of organ transplants. However, the number of patients who require organ
transplants exceeds the number of organs available, particularly if the patient
has a rare blood type or belongs to an ethnic minority where organ donations
are even lower than normal. For example, although black people are three times
more likely than the general population to develop kidney failure, and the
Asian community has a particularly high demand for organs, organ donation
within these groups is relatively low. It is important for the donor and
recipient to have the same blood type and similar genetic make-up in order to
minimize the change of the receiver’s body rejecting the organ. More than
10,000 people in the UK currently need a transplant, and 1,000 people die every
year while on the waiting list. In the US, over 100,000 people are still on the
waiting list. Although these figures are astonishing in themselves, the genuine
figure is probably higher, inflated by the deaths of patients who are never
waitlisted for a transplant. Some patients are never placed on the waiting list
because they have certain habits – such as smoking – and the precious few
organs available are prioritised for patients who fit recipient categories.
The sale of human
organs offers a possible solution to this crippling shortage of organs. There
is already an established black market trade in organs. Entrepreneurs offer
British and Western patients the opportunity to receive privately financed transplants
in countries such as India and Malaysia. In 2006, investigators discovered that
Chinese hospitals were providing organ transplants using the organs of executed
prisoners. In 1983, Dr. Barry Jacobs requested that the US government should
create a fund to compensate the families who donate the organs of their
deceased relatives. He also proposed a business plan to buy kidneys from living
donors to transplant to American patients. However, these is still plenty of
opposition to these ideas, and the National Organ Transplantation Act of 1984
still prohibits the sale of human organs from both dead and living donors.
The proposition line could argue that organs are the property of the
donors, and so they have a right to do with them as they wish. In this case of
buying human organs, it is much easier to argue that the profits would go to
the donor rather than (for example) hospitals or governments which may not have
a vested interest in those concerned. It would be useful to outline in the
mechanism that these organs will be transferred through a unique medical group
or business which has the technology available to match up donors to potential
recipients and so avoid potential medical complications as far as possible.
After this, it would be like any other financial transaction. This debate will
focus on the United Kingdom, but the arguments would be relevant to most
countries considering this policy change.
Pros
|
Cons
|
We already recognize the benefits of individuals who
are able to pay for their healthcare doing so. The ethics of private healthcare are not in question here; indeed, the
UK government has stated that as many people as possible should be encouraged
to pay for private healthcare in order to relieve the strain on national
resources. Critics have understood this as the government prolonging waiting
lists until the patients ‘remove themselves’ either by going private, or
dying. There is, however, a general understanding that the NHS in the UK is
overburdened and that increased private healthcare would help to balance
this. Meanwhile, in the US, private healthcare is the norm. Allowing the sale
of organs is merely an extension of this principle and provides utilitarian
benefit. Not only would those who are able to pay for an organ enjoy a much
better chance at recovery, but there would be more time, space, and resources
for the people who could not afford to do this privately.
|
If payment-for-organs is introduced as a general norm,
this will extend to the state-financed hospitals which are so burdened in the
first place. Few families would turn down the opportunity to receive
‘compensation’ or payment for the families of their loved ones which could
ensure financial stability, particularly if the family member who died was
the sole or main earner. Therefore, either these families will charge the
hospitals the same prices, or they will refuse to donate the organs, and turn
to a private market instead. Given that the black market price for organs can
reach tens of thousands of pounds, it seems unlikely that struggling health
systems would be able to afford it, and this would only encourage an
incredibly harmful disparity between the wealthiest and the poorest. Unless
the proposition case wants to argue that a rich person inherently has a
greater right to an organ than a poor person, their point falls.
|
Legalising the sale of organs will eradicate the black
market and ensure safer transplants. Legalisation can help to eliminate the corruption currently associated
with the organ market. It can also make it easy to regulate, and so safer.
Given the mystery of the black market, medical complications are much more
likely; it is necessary to match the donor and recipient together, but this
cannot be easily done when every step of the organ collection and donation
must be hidden for fear of prosecution. Legalisation could also stop the
‘theft’ or organs and abuse of people like Chinese prisoners who are
currently exploited for their organs – authorities will become accountable to
a publicly recognised and enforced system.
|
If certain people are already risking punishment by
harvesting and transplanting organs illegally, it seems unlikely that they
will suddenly become accountable to a system that recognises that organs can
be bought and sold arbitrarily. If Chinese officials are already suspected of
these activities, it would be very difficult to ensure that profit from the
donated organs did go to the donors or their families rather than corrupt
authorities. Finally, legalizing an action that is currently carried out in
appalling conditions essentially legitimizes appalling human rights
violations, and allows human sacrifice.
|
People should have rights over their own body and body
parts. The proposition is not concerned with live people
trying to donate their hearts, or other vital organs which they cannot live
without. No matter how impoverished that person might be, they will not
choose certain death for a cash payoff. However, organs like kidneys, and
sections of liver, can be and often are donated from a live donor without
significant lasting damage. It is patronising to forbid an individual to sell
or donate an organ when it is possible for them to live without it.
Similarly, the family of a deceased relative, as next of kin, should have the
right to receive financial remuneration from their organs.
|
The state often denies individuals the right to do
certain things with their bodies. For example, the state makes hard drugs
illegal because it recognizes that sometimes individuals do not make the best
decisions for their health or lifestyle choices, and that the physical damage
to their bodies is often lasting and life-changing in ways which that
individual did not apprehend. Furthermore, somebody who is selling an organ
to try and pay off debts or to relieve financial pressure is unlikely to be
thinking entirely rationally; this is an incredibly extreme measure, and
allowing individuals to take control over it for a cash reward is a dangerous
way to create an incentive to cause bodily harm.
|
The donor should be able to benefit financially, rather
than being expected to donate organs with no reward. Given that the doctors, nurses and surgeons who work
around organ transplants are all paid, it is nonsensical that the donor, the
most important figure in the organ transplant, should be left out. The United
States already allows markets for sperm, blood, human eggs and surrogate
wombs. There is no good reason why organs should be excluded when these other
human products are not; there is no moral difference between a kidney and an
ovum. Moreover, organ donation is a lifesaving process, whereas sperm and egg
donation are not. Simply put, incentivizing donations through payment will
save the lives of many patients in need. The payment from these organs could
also hugely improve the quality of life of the donors by lifting them out of
debt, or allowing struggling individuals, such as students, to improve their
career potential by paying for their university fees.
|
It is exactly because organs are potentially
life-saving that it would be dangerous to legalize their sale. Sperm and egg
donations are a last resort for a couple struggling with infertility; they
have had time to weigh their options. Similarly, when sperm, blood or eggs
are donated, they regenerate – kidneys do not. When an organ is the only and
final chance for the patient’s recovery, the patient loses rationality and
becomes desperate to obtain one – to the point where the donors can
essentially name any exploitative price he or she likes. Not only are these
individuals then exploited, and the poorer patients left to die, but
hospitals will be unable to afford them – so the overall chance of a patient
receiving an organ will plummet for the majority without the money to pay for
it.
|
It is just as bad to forbid those who can afford to buy
an organ from taking a life-saving action as it is to allow poorer people to
die. In an ideal world, there would be unlimited organs; but as organ
shortages continue, if anybody can afford to skip the queue by buying an
organ – whether they are generally rich or poor – we should allow them to do
so.
|
Allowing the sale of
organs will harm state-financed health services and create a two-tier system. There is almost no chance that a state-financed health
service will be able to afford the prohibitive cost of purchasing organs
under this model. While it is difficult to track the exact price of organs on
the black market, they often reach many thousands of pounds and there is no
reason to believe that the proposition’s model would suddenly reduce this
price. In effect, this would turn essential organs into luxury items which
the state cannot afford to provide, and so the poorest and neediest would be
left to die. This would condone the most gross discrimination between rich
and poor where a rich life, perhaps even despite a previously neglectful
lifestyle (for example drinking and smoking), could be prioritised over a
poor person’s life where their medical condition may not have been caused by
their lifestyle choices.
|
Given the necessity of a close match between donor and
recipient blood types, and a higher rate of transplant success within the
same race rather than between races, it is a huge exaggeration to imply that
people in poor countries, such as African states, will be scavenged for organs.
Donors from these countries simply will not always match the medical
requirements of Western recipients. In fact, if the organ did match, the
balance of harms still falls in favour of donation. While the donor should
obviously be paid the amount (or very close to, given administration and
surgical costs) paid by the recipient, $10,000 to a struggling family in an
impoverished country could literally be a life-changing opportunity to lift
them out of poverty. In this case, while there may be financial pressure to
donate, it is still a reasoned and logical trade-off for financial security
for a family, and could greatly improve quality of life for both donor and
recipient.
|
Allowing the sale of human organs in the First World
will impact negatively on the Third World. The existing black market already shows a firm flow of organs in one
direction; from the Third World to the First. Those who battle with poverty
in poor countries will see the opportunity to sell their organs to the
wealthy West; however, current disparities between how much donors are paid
for their organs and how much these are then sold on for shows that the
donors are already exploited. Levy Izhak Rosenbaum, a New York City resident,
was accused of paying poor donors in Israel $10,000 for a kidney but charging
up to $160,000 to recipients. There is no reason to believe, even if we
legalize and regulate the organ trade within Western countries, that people
in poorer countries will not continue to be exploited in this manner when
they do not share the same legislation as us.
|
Would the idea of ‘presumed consent’ stand up in any
other area of the law, particularly in cases considering a drastic action
performed on the body? The BMA system completely undermines the UK’s current
conception of consent, particularly that you ‘must be given enough
information to enable you to make a decision’. There is no way to assess if a
patient who has not opted-out of a system like the BMA proposes has truly had
enough knowledge of the subject to make an informed decision – especially
considering that 36% of the nationwide survey conducted by UK Transplant
‘were unaware the NHS Organ Donor Register existed’. Until the general public
has a much, much better understanding of the donor system – in which case
most citizens would likely opt-in anyway – this system is inherently flawed.
Moreover, the potential impact on a grieving family, if they find out that
their relative’s organs had been ‘presumptively’ taken, is very serious.
Family objections are already a problem even in cases where the relative
actively opted-in; this would continue to cause greater outrage if the BMA
system were implemented.
|
There are better solutions to the problems of organ
shortages, such as the BMA system of ‘presumed consent’. The British Medical Association (BMA) is pushing to
introduce a policy of ‘presumed consent’, whereby organs may be taken from a
patient who has died unless they expressly registered their objection to this
before their death. Given that a far larger percentage of people indicate
that they would be happy to donate than the percentage who actually do
donate, this scheme could combat apathy on behalf of the general society and
encourage them to act rather than ignoring or forgetting the option to donate
their organs. This is particularly true in the categories of people who said
that they ‘didn’t know how to register’, ‘had never thought about joining’ or
who ‘hadn’t got round to it’ – comprising a total of 53% of the participants
in the NHS nationwide survey. This scheme could have an enormous impact in
saving the lives of others through a much greater number of available organs.
Several countries, including Spain and Austria have already adopted an
opt-out system, and studies have shown that this policy has caused a dramatic
increase in the number of donations. We can solve the organ shortage without
all of the problems inherent in the proposition’s proposal.
|
Even if there is not an ‘absolute’ right of property
over organs, we still grant individuals to actively choose organ donation, or
to refuse to. In this way, we do accept that each individual has a practical
say over the use of their physical body, just as we must gain consent from a
patient to allow a medical procedure, or allow him or her to refuse it. There
is a huge tangible benefit in this motion – namely that fewer people will die
when there is the option for them to receive organs – and this should take
precedent over complicated legal theory which is often inconclusive one way
or another. Just because law and philosophy do not definitively grant a right
of property over the body, they do not definitively deny it either. The
balance of harms lies firmly in favour of the motion because more people
benefit, either financially or medically.
|
Individuals do not have an inviolable right of property
over their organs. The notion of
property over body parts is very complex, both legally and philosophically.
Generally, judges have shown ‘abhorrence’ at the idea of defining human
bodies or parts of, whether living or dead, as ‘goods or materials’; if a
right to property over the body could ever be exercised, it appears most
strongly where the individual shows ‘no intention of abandoning or donating
it’. While this continues to be an incredibly complex issue, it essentially demonstrates
that there is no absolute right of property over an individual’s own body
parts; it is open to interpretation in each case. A proposition line that
grants authority to any potential donor over the selling of organs assumes a
right of property which does not, in fact, exist. As such it can, and should,
be prevented.
|
0 Comments